Saturday, September 30, 2023

Are We Drugging Revolutionary Potential Out of Our Children?

I was listening to an ADHD podcast and the expert said “unfairness” is a common “trigger” for angry emotions and disregulation. Also people with ADHD are more prone to “Oppositional Defiance Disorder” (ODD) which to me seems like such a made-up condition for people who resist authority. ADHD is commonly treated with medication.

I worry that we will gradually drug the revolutionary impulse (agitation for change) out of our population.
Here’s what worries me: All knowledge  arises in the context of a system of power. In our age power is diffused throughout the system and operates in schools, hospitals, work, etc. (See Foucalt.) 
When we give children medication at least one purpose is to regulate their behavior. This is pretty explicit. ADHD and ODD are defined and diagnosed by reference to certain aberrant behaviors. We talk about helping children “self-regulate” which is (again at least in part) the child internalizing her own subjugation making her her own jailer (with is how power is exercised in the modern era). “Regulation” in the form of thousands of small corrections and incentives is the norm in the modern era (as opposed to past forms of power which relied on much more brutal but less systematic punishment). For this reason Foucault says schools look like prisons and prisons look like schools. Power is less brutal but far more pervasive and omnipresent (E.g. the panopticon). 
When we give children medication to modulate their behavior and emotions (even if we aren’t turning them into compliant zombies) we should be honest about what we are doing. We are contributing to the efficient regulation of the child in the system. This is not necessarily a bad motive. We want our children to be successful. Medication may very well make them happier both in the short and long term. (My unmedicated ADHD child apparently regularly cries at school so it’s not like I’m winning parenting). But again I worry we may be sacrificing revolutionary potential for better regulation—many revolutionaries did not fit very well in the system and sublimated their pain into great deeds and creations. (Leonardo likely had ADHD and was very much outside his system: gay, bastard, little traditional education, failed to follow in the family tradition of distinguished notaries. Hamilton had a similar outsider paradigm that pushed him to greatness.)
Are we denying unique (outsider) children the pain that could make them truly great?


Sunday, June 27, 2021

An Arendtian Critique of U.S. STEM Immigration Policy

 

An Arendtian Critique of U.S. STEM Immigration Policy

 

By Zachary C. Myers

 

“If you catch me at the border, I got visas in my name.

If you come around here, I make 'em all day!

Get one done in a second if you wait.”

              

--M.I.A.[1] 

 

“The fundamental deprivation of human rights is manifested first and above all in the deprivation of a place in the world which makes opinions significant and actions effective.”

 

--Hannah Arendt[2]

 

I.                INTRODUCTION

 

American businesses want to hire more foreign-born workers trained in Science, Technology, Engineering, and Mathematics (“STEM”).[3] Microsoft CEO, Bill Gates, has personally entreated Congress to increase the number of employment based visas available for such workers.[4] A representative from Facebook reported that it nearly outsourced a project when it thought it would be unable to obtain a visa for a critical member of its team.[5]

 

Approximately forty-percent of the nation’s STEM graduate students are foreign nationals.[6] In some fields the proportion is even higher.[7] For example, in electrical engineering, 70.3% of all graduate students are foreign nationals.[8] If these foreign nationals are unable to immigrate to the United States, the country may suffer a “brain drain” as large numbers of U.S.-educated STEM graduates are forced to leave the country.[9]

 

The U.S. legislature has responded to the desire of businesses to hire foreign-born STEM workers, and to the risk of brain-drain from U.S. universities, by proposing several bills to increase the number of foreign-born STEM professionals that are permitted to live in the United States.[10]

 

STEM workers that seek to immigrate to the United States are generally highly educated individuals.[11] Many of them have been educated in the United States, and consider this their home.[12] Because these highly educated individuals are accustomed to the “human artifice” that is unique to the United States, they suffer a great deal when they are denied participation in public life.[13] However, STEM graduates are often discussed in a way that focuses on their usefulness as workers in U.S. society.[14] This narrow focus on “work” ignores the other components of the human condition of immigrants.[15] Specifically, this paper will argue, that by emphasizing immigrants work, U.S. immigration policy fails to maximize STEM immigrants participation in public affairs.[16]

 

Susan F. Martin, believes it is a priority to maximize immigrant participation in the public affairs of their adopted communities.[17] Martin is the Director for the Study of International Migration in the School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University, and the former Executive Director of the U.S. Commission on Immigration Reform, where she advised Congress and the President on immigration policy.[18] For Martin, the key policy question facing the nation is not whether to open-up immigration, but how to integrate immigrants into a national community.[19]

 

Martin uses a three-part descriptive system to explain her ideas. She uses the early immigration policies of colonial Pennsylvania, Massachusetts, and Virginia as archetypes of immigration policy.[20] The Pennsylvania system was the most inclusive immigration system, and provided relatively diverse immigrants with roughly equal rights. Massachusetts, on the other hand, had a more exclusive immigration policy, which excluded people based on ideology, and permanently excluded outsiders from participation in political affairs. Virginia, was more like Pennsylvania than Massachusetts, in that it encouraged immigration; however, unlike Pennsylvania, it did so in order to exploit immigrants as cheap labor.[21]

 

Like Martin, the renowned philosopher, Hannah Arendt has developed a three-part system to describe why it is important for people to participate in public institutions. [22] This is an interesting coincidence that yields fruitful comparisons.

 

Arendt three-part descriptive-system involves the following categories of human activity: “labor,” “work,” and “action.”[23] The first category, labor, is any activity which sustains biological life.[24] The second category, work, is any activity in which humans create durable objects that are not intended primarily for consumption.[25] The third category, action, is any public act that discloses an individual personality and has the potential to give birth to something entirely new.[26] These three conditions are all necessary conditions for human life (as opposed to animal or supernatural life).[27] Of the three categories, action is the most important, because it is the activity that gives meaning to individual human lives.[28]

 

Arendt’s conditions of human life—labor, work, and action—correspond somewhat with Susan Martin’s three type immigration systems—Virginia, Massachusetts, and Pennsylvania—because Virginia’s system exploited immigrants for their labor (especially in the form of slavery); whereas, Pennsylvania expanded immigrants opportunities for action, by giving them access to the public life of the community.[29] Therefore, the immigration system of Pennsylvania best realizes Hannah Arendt’s ideal of maximizing participation in action.[30] For Arendt, individuals must have opportunities to reveal their character in public spaces, or else they will not live full and complete lives.[31] Therefore, an opportunity to participate in politics is extremely important.

 

In order to increase access to civic institutions, legislative proposals should be viewed through the lens of the Pennsylvania, Massachusetts, and Virginia models of immigration.[32] The best proposals for increasing the availability of foreign born STEM workers move our immigration system closer to the more inclusive Pennsylvania model, because this model maximizes participation in public life.[33] U.S. lawmakers should use the Pennsylvania model as a guide to prevent STEM workers from being exploited for their work, and to allow them to lead meaningful lives.

 

II.             ARENDT’S THREE CATEGORIES OF THE HUMAN CONDITION

 

According to Hannah Arendt the human condition is made-up of three activities: labor, work, and action.[34] All three activities, labor, work, and action, are necessary components of “human” life.[35] It is unclear whether Arendt believes that a person would be able to live a life that is completely lacking labor, or work, or action.[36] However, if it is possible, then such a life would be something other than “human.”[37]

a.     The Human Condition of Labor

 

The human condition of labor relates to the biological process of human life.[38] Examples of labor include toiling to produce food, eating, and sleeping. Despite the negative connotation associated with “labor,” for Arendt, labor can actually be quite pleasurable, and is necessary for happiness.[39] One who toils to produce food and is able to savor the fruit of her labors, will feel satisfied and physically nourished.[40] The pleasures and pain involved in labor are sensations that humans share with animals: the pleasure of reproductive sex, along with the pain of childbirth; the pain of toiling for food, along with the pleasure of a hearty meal.[41] Arendt describes people caught-up in labor as “animal laborans.” [42] Because labor relates to the biological process, and is shared with all animals, it unites people with nature and with nature’s earth.[43]

 

Labor is an essential component of a happy human life. “There is no lasting happiness outside the prescribed cycle of painful exhaustion and pleasurable regeneration.”[44] The deprivation of labor comes in two forms: (1) people can be deprived of physical needs, and waste in misery and hunger or, (2) they can have their needs satisfied so readily that there is no need for exertion.[45] “Great riches and an entirely effortless life where boredom takes the place of exhaustion and where the mills of necessity, of consumption and digestion, grind an impotent human body mercilessly and barrenly to death—ruins the elemental happiness that comes from being alive.”[46] A life without labor, whether because of deprivation or because of overindulgence, is a miserable existence.[47]

 

While labor is an essential component of a fulfilling existence, on its own, labor will not produce a meaningful human life. Labor is ruled by necessity. [48] Humans must eat to survive. Seeds must be planted in the spring, watered during the summer, and harvested in the fall. Therefore, while labor can be pleasurable, it is never freedom. One does not choose to eat. One must eat. Because labor is always governed by necessity, it is never a free act.[49] A person who merely labors, like an animal, does not have a bios, or life story.[50] They are merely producing and consuming, feeding the incessant cycle of biological life.[51] Therefore, those whose lives are spent exclusively in labor are mere biological animals, at one with nature, but not participating in a human life.[52] In order to have a human life, a person must be removed from nature and participate in the world, which is the space of human affairs. [53]

 

b.     The Human Condition of Work

 

The activity that removes humans from nature and places them in the world is work.

 

The human condition of work relates to the creation of durable goods that form a world in which people interact.[54] Examples of work include fabricating tools, reproducing books, and building dwellings and monuments. By engaging in work, human beings create durable objects, which relate human beings to one another.[55] Additionally, durable objects permit human words and deeds to live on long after the author is dead.[56]

 

By creating durable objects that will outlive their creators, work removes humans from nature and allows them to participate in immortality. [57] Without work, human beings would be no different than animal life, living and dying following the cyclical repetition of nature.[58] By creating a world (separate from nature’s earth) work elevates and separates the animal laborans from nature and makes them human. [59] This world both connects and separates individuals—allowing them to relate to each other through it, and also distinguish themselves as individuals by retrieving their identity  in relation to specific durable objects:[60]

 

“[T]he things of the world have the function of stabilizing human life, and their objectivity lies in the fact that—in contradiction to the Heraclitean saying that the same man can never enter the same stream—men their ever-changing nature notwithstanding, can retrieve their sameness, that is their identity, by being related to the same chair and the same table.”[61]

 

Nature is constantly in flux.[62] Without a durable world, humans would be caught in that flux and unable to distinguish themselves as individuals.[63] Arendt does not outright criticize nomadic life, but clearly finds a durable, demarcated world, stabilized by “property,” to be an ideal.[64] (Property here is similar to Radin’s concept property, where personhood is established through a relation to places and objects.[65] Consumptive goods do not qualify as property, because consumption is actually destructive of the relationship between personhood and stable objects.[66])

 

Work’s guiding principle is usefulness.[67] Work relates to Aristotle’s techne, or technology.[68] For Arendt, like Aristotle, durable objects each have a telos, or end purpose.[69] The purpose of each object is its use by people.[70] The products of work have an “objectivity” based on this telos.[71] Every product of work exists in the mind’s eye of the fabricator, or homo faber, based on its useful purpose.[72] If an object is not useful, then the worker has failed.[73] For instance, an object that is not useful for sitting cannot be called a chair.[74] Therefore, work creates the object-ivity of the world—the use of objects permit humans to interact and relate to each other.

 

Work produces objective forms in the mind’s eye of people as homo faber, but work does not give birth to anything new.[75] It is strictly regulated by utility.[76] (If an object is not useful, than the worker has failed.)[77] Because work is regulated by utility, the activity of the work is not free.[78]

 

Additionally, because work is techne, a life of work is highly susceptible to critique based on the problems inherent in technology.[79] Technology destroys the meaningfulness of natural objects.[80] Work removes material from nature, and robs them of their meaning as natural objects.[81] Everything is mere material for fabrication, or “standing-reserve,” in the hand of people as homo faber.[82]

 

Like labor, work is necessary component of a human life.  However, a life filled with work alone is not meaningful, because work done solely for the sake of utility collapses into a self-referential void.[83] Arendt states that “[t]he perplexity of utilitarianism is that it gets caught in the unending chain of means and ends without ever arriving at some principle which could justify the category of means and end, that is, of utility itself.”[84] Work does not supply a reason for working.[85] Unlike labor, which is done out of necessity, work is done merely because it is useful, but there is no use for usefulness.[86] Something else must supply a purpose for which a thing is useful.[87] There must be something “for the sake of” which work is done, which must come from something other than work.[88] A life that is spent being useful in order to be useful is not meaningful.[89]

 

Because work cannot supply meaning to human life, and actually tends to destroy the meaningfulness of the natural world, the activity of homo faber is not sufficient on its own to constitute a meaningful human life.[90]

 

c.      The Human Condition of Action

 

Action gives meaning to human life. Actions are words and deeds that are done in public that reveal a person’s character.[91] Because action is done publicly, and other people are able to respond to one’s action, it always has the potential to give birth to something entirely new. One of the clearest examples of action in Arendt’s work is making and keeping promises in order to constitute public bodies.[92] The revelatory and spontaneous character of action makes it the most meaningful component of human life.

 

Action does not include all words and deeds, but are instead the words and deeds that constitute a person’s life story, which will live-on after they have died. [93] They constitute a person’s bios, or social and biographical life, and are opposed to zoÄ“, or mere biological life.[94] Actions are “at home in everlastingness,” because they are worthy of being remembered.[95] Through action, individual human lives become permanently fixed in eternity.[96] Unlike the circular progression of the stars, the changing of the seasons, and the continuous death and rebirth of animals in nature, which all follow a cyclical pattern, an individual human life is linear.[97] It has a beginning and an end. It is a singularity, which cuts across nature’s cycles.[98] It is only because humans participate in action that their lives have this quality. A person who did nothing but toil for food and shelter, sleep, and fuck, without engaging in thought, word, or deed, would not be properly human at all, but would be a mere animal laborans, completely caught in nature’s cycle.[99] Similarly, a solitary worker who had no words or deeds would not be a human, but a god, building a world in which other humans can act, but without herself acting in that world.[100] Only by virtue of one’s “active life” is a linear bios created in the world, which can cut across the circular progression of nature.[101]

 

Action is not reactive and is different than mere “behavior.”[102] An example of action is forgiveness:

 

“In contrast to revenge, which is the natural, automatic re-action to transgression, and which  because of the irreversibility of the action process can be expected and even calculated, the act of forgiving can never be predicted; it is the only reaction that acts in an unexpected way and thus retains, though being a reaction, something of the original character of action.”[103]

 

Forgiveness breaks the chain reaction of revenge, an eye for an eye, and has the potential to give birth to something new.[104] Therefore, forgiveness is a uniquely human act that reveals an individual character.[105] This example helps illustrates the narrowness of Arendt’s concept of action.[106] Most human activity is merely “behavior,” which is predictable and reactive and does not reveal individuality, personal character, or distinction.[107] Action, on the other hand, is a narrow category of revelatory acts worthy of being recorded, because they reveal a human will.[108]

 

Action is strictly separated from labor and work. [109] Unlike labor, and work, action is not motivated by necessity or usefulness.[110] Nothing necessary or useful has the requisite spontaneity and mark of individuality to be called action, because actions are unique to humans as individuals, and express an individual character.[111]

 

Even though action is never labor or work, it is dependent on both labor and work. Before an individual can act without regard to necessity, biological necessity must be satisfied.[112] Therefore, labor, which satisfies biological necessity, is a precondition to action.[113] Likewise, action requires a shared world, within which people can interact and publicly reveal their character.[114] By constituting a world of durable goods, work creates the stage, and the conditions, for action.[115]

 

Because labor and work are necessary conditions for action, the three categories roughly corresponds with the higher categories of need in Maslow’s hierarchy of needs.[116] Like love, esteem, and self-actualization (Maslow); actions (Arendt) are not possible if a person is constantly preoccupied with “physiological needs” (Maslow) or labor (Arendt).[117] Like love, esteem, and self-actualization, which are extremely threatened by loss of freedom, action also requires the negative freedoms, such as freedom of movement, and speech.[118] Additionally, action is only possible where there is a community of equals.[119] (A competitive community of equals).[120] Therefore, action is not possible under conditions of violence or bondage.

 

However, action is not synonymous with the higher categories of need.[121] Love, esteem, and self-actualization can be developed privately by oneself, or among intimate friends or lovers.[122] These needs are generally not a matter of public concern.[123] Action, on the other hand, is always public.[124] Additionally, Maslow’s “needs” cannot be harmonized with Arendt’s concept of action, because action is never taken in response to a necessity (“need”), but is a pure expression of an individual character, or will. [125]

 

In order to become free from necessity, a precondition for action, the ancients used violence.[126] Violence was used to force one person to care for another person’s biological needs, i.e. to force one’s “labor” onto another.[127] Arendt describes this “violence” as “the prepolitical act of liberating oneself from the necessity of life for the freedom of the world.”[128] Arendt does not consider violence a political action.[129] However, while violence is not action, it was a necessary condition for action for ancient humans.[130] By subjugating and ruling over other people, ancient Greeks were able to overcome necessity and usefulness and engage in action.[131] Arendt goes so far as to say that “because all human beings are subject to necessity, they are entitled to violence towards others.”[132] This is a perplexing statement. No person is “entitled” to the labor of another through violence.[133] Furthermore, Arendt approves of the peoples’ councils formed by laborers and workers, such as early soviets in Russia,[134] popular societies in France,[135] townhalls in North America,[136] and workers’ councils in Hungary.[137] She recognizes these as authentic sites of action.[138] People who are members of a laboring class often have ample leisure to speak, reason together, and make promises, i.e. act, when they have completed their day’s labor.[139] Therefore, it is unclear why only a ruling class that has subjugated a laboring class can be freed from necessity sufficient to engage in action.

 

However, if a laboring class’s labor is too burdensome, individuals will not have time to organize and act among each other.[140] Furthermore, the soviets, popular societies, townhalls, and workers’ councils were short-lived and appeared during revolutionary periods when everyday life was interrupted.[141] When the initial revolution ended, the laboring class went home.[142] Therefore, Arendt took seriously the idea that only an elite class will be able to engage in action.[143] However, others have argued that some of the most genuine sites of action today exist in conditions of poverty, and can continue to exist so long as they are not subjugated by force.[144] Arendt may have mistaken a historical reality—that free people have often enjoyed extra leisure at the expense of a laboring class—for a historical necessity—that freedom is only possible after one group has subjugated another in order to provide ample leisure.[145] Action is possible wherever people gather together as equals without being dominated by necessity or usefulness.[146]

 

Regardless of whether Arendt believes subjugation of a laboring class is a necessary condition to elevate a ruling class to a site of action, it is clear that “slavish” meaning a life ruled by labor and necessity is undesirable.[147] “The slave’s degradation was a blow of fate and a fate worse than death, because it carried with it a metamorphosis of man into something akin to a tame animal.”[148] A life ruled by labor was not “worse than death” because it was difficult, but because it was not free.[149] This is not solely, or even primarily, a negative freedom in terms of free movement and commerce, but a positive freedom to reveal one’s character through word and deed. [150] “A poor free man preferred the insecurity of a daily-changing labor market to regular assured work, which, because it restricted his freedom to do as he pleased every day, was already felt to be servitude (douleia), and even harsh, painful labor was preferred to the easy life of many household slaves.”[151] Not only was grueling labor preferred to servitude, day wages, which were a less stable source of revenue, were preferred to continuous employment.[152] The ancients Greeks understood that an agent of another person is not able to reveal her personal character.[153] The ancient attitude toward freedom was such that a free workman was also willing to do much more arduous work, and avoid stable employment, in order to maintain the dignity of free action.[154]

 

 Not everything that is said or done in public deserves to be called ‘action.’[155] A true act must be some form of word or deed that reveals a person’s character, is not done out of necessity or usefulness, has the potential to give birth to something entirely new, and is at home in everlastingness. Despite being a narrow category of activity, action gives meaning to human life.[156]

 

“The unexamined life is not worth living for a human being.”[157] A meaningful human life requires action. However, action requires a “stage” upon which individuals can publicly reveal their character.[158] Arendt calls these stages “spaces of freedom” and compares them to “islands in a sea or as oases in a desert.”[159] The challenge for policy-makers is to maximize these “spaces of freedom,” and enlarge participation in public life.[160]

 

III.           MARTIN’S MODELS OF IMMIGRATION

 

Martin has developed a descriptive theory of immigration policy based on the colonial immigration policies of Virginia, Massachusetts, and Pennsylvania.[161] None of Fuchs’s & Martin’s models are ‘anti’-immigration; Martin avoids the ‘anti’/‘pro’-immigration binary. Instead, her theory addresses not whether STEM workers should be admitted to the United States, but instead how they should be admitted?[162]

 

a.     Virginia

 

The Virginia model represents the wrong way to admit immigrants to the United States. Virginia’s immigration policy was solely concerned with obtaining cheap, reliable laborers.[163] Immigration policies in Virginia encouraged the importation of labor using the most inexpensive means possible, and then permitted exploitation of laborers.[164] Virginia permitted the exploitation of cheap labor using three programs:  (1) indentured servitude, (2) the importation of convicts and debtors to the colony, and, (3) through slavery.[165] Slavery, in particular, epitomized the Virginia models focus on cheap labor without regard for immigrant welfare.[166] Yet, treatment of indentured servants and convicts was also extremely harsh.[167] Many died as a result of this treatment.[168] Virginia was not interested in creating a tolerant, pluralistic society; instead, they were focused on creating a pliant, reliable, non-citizen workforce for the plantations.[169]

 

            The Virginia Model of immigration is related to the human condition of labor. Like the system employed by ancient Greeks, the entrepreneurs of the Virginia colony relied on an underclass to provide labor, so that they were freed to pursue other pursuits.[170] For instance, Thomas Jefferson is one of Arendt’s classic examples of a man of action;[171] He was also a man of slaves.[172] While slavery elevated several men to a position where they were empowered to live active lives, full of great words and deeds, their slaves were subject to a “fate worse than death.”[173] “[T]he institution of slavery carries an obscurity even blacker than the obscurity of poverty; the slave, not the poor man, was ‘wholly overlooked.’”[174] Slaves lived their lives in ignominy, and died without having had an opportunity to participate in public civic institutions.[175]

 

b.     Massachusetts

 

While Pennsylvania’s immigration model fostered ideological pluralism, the Massachusetts’s model maintained an ideologically ‘pure’ population.[176] “Membership in the Massachusetts Bay Company was based on religious qualifications.”[177] Massachusetts, led by John Winthrop, recruited like-minded individuals in an effort to create “a city upon a hill,” a society of true, Puritan believers.[178] Massachusetts even resorted to exclusionary policies to cultivate this ideal, by expelling people with whom they did not agree.[179] Dissenters, like Roger Williams and Anne Hutchinson, were expelled from the community and deported.[180]

 

Unlike immigrants to Pennsylvania, immigrants to Massachusetts were only extended membership if they met certain rigid ideological categories.[181] There were four categories of colonists in Massachusetts:

 

“First were the freemen, who alone could vote for governor, magistrates, and colony as a whole. Second were church members who did not become freeman. … Third were those who were neither church members nor freemen but took an oath of fidelity to the colony and shared its aims... Fourth were those who did not take an oath of fidelity; they were … ‘in the colony but not of it.’”[182]

 

Ideological exclusion and deportation characterized the immigration model of Massachusetts.

 

            Massachusetts is related to the human condition of work. Unlike, Virginia, which very explicitly created a laboring class which lived in ignominy, Massachusetts permitted citizens to participate in the colony as workers.[183] Skilled craftsmen were free to build durable goods and contributed to separate the Puritan colony from nature, but they were not permitted to participate in the governance of the colony.[184]

 

            Because immigrants to Massachusetts enjoyed a great deal more negative freedom, such as freedom of movement, and freedom to participate in the economics of the colony, the immigrants to Massachusetts were much better off compared to immigrants in Virginia.[185] Yet, Massachusetts immigrants were still excluded from the public square. Only the men with puritan credentials were permitted to join the council of “freemen” who met together in a community of equals to speak in public, make promises (and compacts) together, and take part in what Arendt called the “good life.”[186] Because non-puritan immigrants were free to participate in the community as skilled workers, but were not given full rights as citizens, immigrants were essentially consigned to the position of homo faber (mere workers).[187]

 

c.      Pennsylvania

 

The Pennsylvania model did not share the Massachusetts’s models focus on religious purity.[188] Instead, the immigration policy of colonial Pennsylvania was integrative, and generally did not discriminate based on ideology.[189] William Penn used immigration policy in Pennsylvania to test his ideas about religious tolerance.[190] He recruited immigrants from all across Europe to populate Pennsylvania.[191] By actively recruiting and accepting immigrants from all of Europe, Penn created a pluralistic society.[192] In order to incentivize immigration, and integrate immigrants into the colony, Pennsylvania offered immigrants roughly equal treatment and rights, including the right to citizenship.[193] Penn’s model was both open to a diverse group of immigrants, and focused on making them long-term permanent residents through integration, and naturalization.[194]

 

The Pennsylvania model is related to the human condition of action. Under the Pennsylvania model, immigrants are accepted as individuals and are given an opportunity to participate in public affairs.[195] By facilitating participation in publicly visible spaces, the Pennsylvania model maximizes human potential for action.[196] Because this model increases access to “spaces of freedom,” it makes it more likely that individuals will be able to live full and complete lives.[197]

 

Arendt actually strongly doubts that the political institutions that currently exist in the United States are up to the task of providing “spaces of freedom” for anyone other than a super-elite group—primarily senators and congresspeople.[198] However, opening up access to whatever limited “oases” of freedom that exist in the United States should be an important policy goal for the sake of maximizing human dignity.[199]

 

Pennsylvania, Massachusetts, and Virginia are useful archetypes for comparing different immigration policy moves.[200] Pennsylvania arises as the preferred immigration model, because it does not rely on ideological restrictions or exploitative labor practices, and it fosters an open pluralistic society of worker-citizens and maximizes freedom through participation in government.[201]

 

IV.           SURVEY OF EXISTING LAW

 

U.S. employers have two options for sponsoring the entrance to the United States of foreign-born STEM workers: they can sponsor them as “immigrants” or as “non-immigrants.” “Non-immigrants,” are defined by a laundry list of categories of people seeking entrance to the United States on a temporary basis. [202] Working backwards from this definition, “an immigrant” is anyone seeking entrance to the United States with the intention to remain indefinitely, i.e. to establish permanent residence.[203] In a case involving an employer sponsoring an alien for admission to the United States for the purpose of employment, applicants can usually apply for entrance as both an immigrant and a non-immigrant.[204]

 

a.     Entrance as an Immigrant

 

Once admitted and inspected an immigrant is a lawful permanent resident (“LPR”) and is permitted to live and work in the United States indefinitely, provided that they do not commit certain crimes.[205] Additionally, an LPR can petition for admittance of family members as immigrants.[206] They can also leave the U.S. for extended period of time (up to a year), and return, without having to apply for readmission.[207] Finally, after five years residence, an LPR can apply for naturalization to obtain full citizenship.[208] Because entering the United States as an immigrant affords general work authorization, indefinite residence status, the ability to petition for the entrance of family members, travel rights, and a clear path to citizenship, STEM workers may prefer to enter the United States as immigrants.

 

Entering the United States as an immigrant affords fairly robust rights to STEM workers, but this route is not always immediately available to those seeking to work in this country. Annual caps limit the number of employment-based immigrants (and family members) that are permitted to move to the United States.[209] Only 65,918 employer-sponsored immigrants (along with their spouses and children) were admitted in 2013.[210] These limited immigration opportunities are allocated according to a priority system.[211] Most STEM workers fall under the second or third priority categories (EB-2 and EB-3) for “aliens who are members of the professions holding advanced degrees or aliens of exceptional ability” and “skilled workers, professionals, and other workers.”[212] EB-2 and EB-3 applicants are each guaranteed approximately 40,000 spots per year (in addition to any spots that are not used by higher priority categories)—80,000 spots out of 140,000.[213]

 

Limits based on country of origin also restrict access to immigrant status. No group of immigrants from any one country can receive more than seven percent of the employment-based immigration spots in a given year.[214] Because visa demand from a few countries greatly exceeds seven percent per year, the national origin restriction has created a bottleneck in the employment-based immigration system. The affected countries are China, India, Mexico, and the Philippines.[215] A STEM worker from China currently faces a backlog of applications going back six years before they can get permanent resident status.[216] Applicants from India face even longer backlogs—applicants that became eligible for immigrant status in March 2013 waited over eleven years for that chance.[217] U.S. employers are highly unlikely to wait eleven years in order to hire an employee through the immigrant process.[218] As a result, eligibility backlogs, and processing times,[219] make it “virtually impossible to hire an individual” through this system.[220] As a result, most STEM workers enter the United States as non-immigrants.[221]

 

b.     Entrance as a “Non-immigrant”

 

Employers are much more likely to hire STEM workers as temporary, non-immigrant, workers,[222] but non-immigrants do not have the robust rights afforded immigrants.[223] Non-immigrant admission statuses are limited to specific times and purposes.[224] There are many non-immigrant statuses,[225] but the two that are most relevant to STEM workers may enter the United States for a temporary period to study at a U.S. University or to work in a “specialty occupation” at a U.S. company.[226] Failure to maintain a full course load or failure to remain employed to a sponsoring employer may violate the terms of a non-immigrant’s admission to the United States, making her removable.[227]

 

Because non-immigrant admission only authorizes temporary residence, many non-immigrant STEM workers attempt to become lawful permanent residents by way of a process called “adjustment of status.”[228] However, backlogs in the employment-based (“EB”) system prevent many non-immigrants from adjusting status for many years.[229]

 

Largely because the EB system fails to accommodate many people seeking adjustment of status, measures are in place to extend non-immigrant students and temporary workers stays in the United States. Changes have been made to make it easier for non-immigrants to change U.S. employers, by allowing them to ‘port’ their H-1B status from one sponsor to the next without waiting for authorization from INS.[230] However, h-1b non-immigrants seeking to change employers still face a significant risk that they will lose lawful status by quitting their job.[231] Non-immigrants admitted to the United States for the purpose of studying at a U.S. University may choose to extend their stay by one year through program called optional practical training (“OPT”). Most students are eligible for a 12-month extension under OPT.[232] STEM students are permitted an even longer extension—17 months.[233] These stop-gap measures have undoubtedly enabled many STEM immigrants to adjust status who would not have been able to do so otherwise,[234] but large backlogs of people seeking adjustment of status continue to be a problem.[235]

 

H-1b has become the vehicle of choice for employers seeking to hire foreign-born STEM workers.[236] However, demand currently outstrips the number of h-1b non-immigrants admitted each year.[237] Demand exceeds the number of applicants admitted, because H-1b admissions have been capped at 65,000 per year.[238] In 2000, in an effort to “clear out the backlog of pending” h-1b applications, Congress increased the cap to 195,000 people per year for three years.[239] However, after three years, the cap reverted to 65,000 admissions.[240] This year the INS stopped giving out visas in June, three months after the start of the season.[241]


 

V.             CRITIQUE OF THE STATUS QUO

 

In order to admit STEM workers to the United States the temporary employment system should be disfavored in favor of the much less used, EB system of immigration, because immigrants under the temporary employment system have limited rights that do not permit them to assimilate into public life and engage in action.

 

Immigrant STEM workers may be in high demand because they are easier to exploit.[242] As explained previously temporary workers have limited rights in the United States. They do not have complete freedom of movement; instead, they are tied to a single U.S. employer, and must obtain special permission in order to change jobs.[243] Because temporary workers immigration rights are tied to continued employment, they have a strong incentive to maintain their job, because losing a job could mean being forced to leave the country.[244] As a result, foreign-born temporary workers are credited with being more “loyal” to their employers compared to native workers.[245] The threat of losing immigration status motivates temporary workers to stay at job longer, regardless of working conditions or relative pay.[246]

 

Some commentators have described temporary work immigration statuses, such as the h-1b, as a form of indentured servitude.[247] “Be wary of H1-B visas in the USA—you basically get shackled to a company . . . being a non-American in the USA is almost like being a second-class citizen,” stated an Australian worker who worked in the United States under the H1-B status.[248] Immigrant STEM workers are not integrated as equals into public life, but are instead relegated to a secondary status, similar to the immigrants in colonial Massachusetts.[249]

 

Temporary work status immigrants do not occupy “spaces of freedom.” They do not enjoy basic rights to movement.[250] They are not secure in their position in the United States, and could be forced to leave simply because they leave their employer or are fired.[251] As a result, they are not able to engage in action.

 

“[T]he faculty of action … can be actualized only in one of the many manifold forms of human community.”[252] The law separates the members of a community from nature.[253] Temporary workers are neither inside, nor outside this community, because they are not permanent members of the community in which they reside. A temporary worker is a “a human being or homo in the original sense of the word, indicating someone outside the range of the law and the body politic of the citizens, as for instance a slave—but certainly a politically irrelevant being.”[254] They are thus stripped of legal personality and exist as mere bare life.[255] Their biological life, work, and labor, are of political significance, but their human life, and action, are irrelevant:

 

“[T]heir freedom of movement, if they have it at all, gives them no right to residence[,] which even the jailed criminal enjoys as a matter of course; and their freedom of opinion is a fool’s freedom, for nothing they think matters anyhow… The fundamental deprivation of human rights is manifested first and above all in the deprivation of a place in the world which makes opinions significant and actions effective… They are deprived not of the right to freedom but of a right to action; not of the right to think whatever they please, but of the right to opinion.” [256]

 

Because temporary workers are not fully part of their communities, their actions are rendered irrelevant.

Immigrants in this status cannot participate in an open market for their services (because they are tied to one employer);[257] they cannot engage in civil disobedience because they can be deported for illegal activity;[258] they can organize, but these organizations are politically irrelevant. [259] Therefore, they cannot exercise power, or freely act. As a result, individuals and the country are deprived of potentialities that might otherwise be opened by these highly educated (and often highly Americanized) individuals.[260] Additionally, there is no reason to record or remember the actions of temporary workers, because they are largely irrelevant to the community.[261] Because their lives are less likely to be remembered, the lives of temporary STEM workers have less meaning than would otherwise be possible if they were full members of the United States.[262]

Because the words and deeds of temporary workers are largely irrelevant, even if the working conditions and treatment of temporary workers happened to be better than the working conditions of U.S. citizens, temporary work status would still be a “fate worse than death,” because, temporary workers would still lead ignominious lives outside the public realm of the United States.[263] They do not have access to spaces of freedom where they could disclose themselves and have a bios.

There are competing explanations for the high demand for foreign born STEM workers in the United States. Foreign born STEM workers may be in high demand because they are easier to exploit.[264] However, foreign-born STEM workers may fill critical niche positions at high-tech companies that cannot be supplied by the domestic labor market.[265] Some STEM workers come to the United States with no intent to permanently immigrate, and are simply filling a temporary technological niche that is desperately needed by a corporation.[266] Such workers may actually have greater mobility than the average American, and the appropriate context for them to exercise freedom of action will be among their peers in their country of origin.[267] Therefore, there likely is an appropriate use for the H1-B, and other temporary worker, non-immigrant statuses.[268] However, because of the potential damaging effects of temporary work status on the lives of immigrants seeking long-term residence in the United States, the temporary work program should be disfavored. 

 

a.     PROPOSALS FOR CHANGE

 

In order to address the apparent demand for foreign-born STEM workers, several bills have been advanced in Congress, which increase the number of STEM workers that are permitted to reside and work in the United States.[269] Two of the most recent proposals are the Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act (“Immigration Modernization Act”) and the Immigration Innovation Act of 2013 (“Immigration Innovation Act).[270] Both acts would expand the amount of STEM workers that would be permitted to permanently immigrate to the United States.

 

                                                  i.     Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act (“Immigration Modernization Act”).

 

The Immigration Modernization Act is intended to be a “comprehensive” immigration reform.[271] The text of the most current version of the bill is almost twelve-hundred pages long.[272] It includes provisions that would utilize National Guard units to assist border patrol, create a non-immigrant category for low-skilled temporary workers and a point-based system to allocate permanent resident status, and of relevance to this paper, it creates a new employment-based immigration category for workers with advanced STEM degrees from U.S. educational institutions.[273]

 

Under this proposal, STEM workers that have advanced degrees (masters or doctorates) from qualifying U.S. Universities and have offers of employment from U.S. employers will almost be guaranteed permanent residence.[274] Instead of being subject to numerical limitations under the second or third employment-based immigration preference category (EB-2 or EB-3), STEM workers will be exempted from numerical limitations.[275] As a result, a great deal more STEM workers will be eligible for permanent residence than are permitted to become LPRs under the status quo.[276]

 

In addition to permitting unlimited immigrant statuses for STEM workers that graduated with advanced degrees from US educational institutions, the Immigration Modernization Act also eliminates per country limits on employment-based immigration.[277] Therefore, immigrants from countries with a large number of applicants, such as India and China, will not be subject to separate limits to immigration.[278] All immigrants will be treated the same regardless of their place of origin.[279] Along with eliminating per country limits, the Immigration Modernization Act also increases (or decreases) the overall employment-based immigration limit based on demand from the previous year.[280] Depending on demand the overall limit could increase to as much as 250,000 people per year.[281] This would greatly reduce the backlog of immigrants seeking LPR status in other categories, such as EB-2 “aliens who are members of the professions holding advanced degrees or aliens of exceptional ability”[282]

 

By providing unlimited LPR statuses to STEM workers that graduate from U.S. educational institutions, and dramatically increasing the number of LPR statuses that will be granted to other employment-based immigrants, the Immigration Modernization Act greatly increases the amount of STEM workers that can come to the United States as permanent residents.

 

                                                ii.     The Immigration Innovation Act of 2013 (“Immigration Innovation Act”)

 

Like the Immigration Modernization Act, the Immigration Innovation Act provides expanded opportunities to STEM workers by creating a new immigration category for STEM workers.[283] However, the special category for STEM workers created by the Immigration Innovation Act is much more limited than the category created under the Immigration Modernization Act, because it is both numerically limited and has additional requirements that STEM workers must meet.[284]

 

The Immigration Innovation Act creates a new immigration status for STEM workers called “conditional permanent residence.”[285] Conditional permanent residence under this category is limited to fifty-thousand STEM graduates per year.[286] Such STEM graduates must have graduated with an advanced degree from a qualified U.S. education institution (same as under the Immigration Modernization Act).[287] Once an individual obtains residence under this category, their residence is limited to either (1) “1 year after the expiration of the alien's student visa … if the alien is diligently searching for an opportunity to become actively engaged in a STEM field;” or (2) for as long as “the alien remains actively engaged in a STEM field.”[288] A STEM worker’s residence in the U.S. under this provision requires active engagement in a STEM field.[289] The term “actively engaged in a STEM field” is not defined; therefore it is not clear how rigorous this requirement will be in practice.[290] Regardless of how strict the requirement of active engagement in a STEM field is in practice, conditional permanent residence is more limited than ordinary LPR-status.[291]

 

Additionally, conditional permanent residents are not eligible for “unemployment compensation … or [] any Federal means-tested public benefit.”[292] Conditional permanent residents are not entitled the same benefits as permanent residents generally.[293]

After five years of active engagement in a STEM field, conditional permanent residents would automatically be converted into ordinary LPRs, if the Immigration Innovation Act became the law of the land.[294]

 

Like the Immigration Modernization Act, the Immigration Innovation Act also eliminates per country limits on employment-based immigration.[295] Therefore, this proposal, like the last, would alleviate the backlogs of permanent residence applications from high-volume employment-based immigration countries, such as India and China.[296]

 

VI.           ANALYSIS OF PROPOSED LEGISLATION REGARDING STEM IMMIGRANTS

 

a.     Improved Opportunities for Action

 

Both immigration categories, under the Immigration Modernization Act and the Immigration Innovation Act, make it much more likely that STEM immigrants will be able to lead active, meaningful lives. By providing STEM workers with much greater access to immigrant status (i.e. permanent residence) STEM workers will have basic rights of movement that are not available to temporary workers. As LPRs STEM workers will be able to reside in the United States indefinitely; their legal residence will not be conditioned on maintaining a specific job or course of study.[297]

 

            While extending LPR status to an immigrant increases their rights of movement and economic rights, these economic rights do not perfectly maximize action, because “the faculty of action … can be actualized only in one of the many manifold forms of human community.”[298] Permanent residents are not complete members of a community composed of citizens. They cannot vote, and they’re ability to engage in civil disobedience is limited, because they can be deported for committing crimes. [299]

 

Even though permanent residence is not complete membership, being granted immigrant status puts STEM workers on a path to full integration through citizenship.[300] After residing in the United States for five years, LPRs are eligible to apply for citizenship.[301] By including immigrants in its community, the Pennsylvania model maximizes the potential for immigrants to engage in action. As citizens, STEM workers will have more opportunity to engage in action and have meaningful lives. They will have equal opportunity to vote, organize politically, and serve in political offices. They will even be able to engage in civil disobedience, without risk of being expelled from the community. They will be complete members, with full access to whatever limited public institutions the U.S. has to offer. Because both the Immigration Modernization Act and the Immigration Innovation Act would increase the opportunity for STEM workers to fully integrate into U.S. citizenry, both proposals bring the U.S. closer to the Pennsylvania model of immigration.

 

The Immigration Modernization Act is particularly good in this regard. It provides unlimited immigration statuses to individuals that graduate with advanced STEM degrees from U.S. universities, and drastically increases the number of other employment-based workers that will be able to obtain immigrant status in the United States.[302] In this way it could change the U.S. employment immigration system from one that relies heavily on (potentially exploitative) temporary worker statuses, into one that actively integrates employment-based immigrants through permanent residence, and eventual citizenship.

 

The Immigration Innovation Act is a weaker proposal than the Immigration Modernization Act. The numerical limits on immigration under the Immigration Innovation Act have the potential to push many STEM immigrants into temporary work statuses, such as the H1-B.[303] Living under a temporary work status makes it much less likely that STEM immigrants will be able to have “active” lives, because their legal status in the country will be unstable (“conditional”).[304] Even if STEM workers are able to obtain conditional permanent residence, the additional conditions for permanent residence undermine the potential for STEM immigrants to have active lives, because residence is conditioned on active engagement in a STEM field. The ambiguity regarding what it means to be “actively engaged in a STEM field” may limit STEM immigrants’ choices and activities; forcing them into a condition similar to temporary workers, where they cannot act freely for fear of losing their employment and their residence status.[305]

 

Additionally, the unequal treatment of conditional permanent residents in regard to government benefits is not like the Pennsylvania model of full integration, and is instead closer to the Virginia model. Conditional permanent residents must work in their field in order to remain in the United States, and are not given access to the social safety net of the community.[306] This is an exploitative, rather than integrative, policy. Rather than limiting the rights of STEM immigrants to the United States (as per the Virginia model), STEM immigrants should be given rights that are roughly equal to those of citizens. By welcoming, and integrating, rather than exploiting STEM immigrants, the U.S. system can move in close alignment with the Pennsylvania model of immigration.

 

VII.        CONCLUSION

 

Employment-based immigration policy can be improved by reducing or eliminating gaps in the process of integration that can permanently relegate immigrants (even highly skilled immigrants) to a pre-political position in society, where action—the content of a meaningful life—is denied. For this reason, the U.S. reliance on a system of temporary work statuses should be eliminated. The proposals regarding STEM graduates analyzed here are both better than the status quo in the United States, but the more comprehensive Immigration Modernization Act is superior to the piecemeal Immigration Innovation Act. It is a more consistent application of the Pennsylvania model, because it actively integrates immigrants by providing them robust rights as immigrants and an opportunity to obtain full membership in the community.



[1] M.I.A., Kala (Interscope Records 2007).

[2] Hannah Arendt, Imperialism: Part Two of the Origins of Totalitarianism 297 (1968)

[3] See, e.g.,  TechNet, TechNet Executives Meet with President Obama; Call on U.S. Policymakers to Spur Innovation Critical to Economic Growth: Over 100 Leading Tech Execs Also Urge Swift Action This Year on High Skilled Immigration Reform, TechNet.org (last accessed March 25, 2013), http://www.technet.org/technet-executives-meet-with-president-obama-call-on-u-s-policymakers-to-spur-innovation-critical-to-economic-growth/; H. Ronald Klasko, Top Five Business Immigration Law Issues: What Employers Need to Know in Today's Economy, 19 Bus. L. Today 11, 14 (2009-2010) (arguing that the current quotas for employment visas “bear no resemblance to business realities.”)

[4] Bill Gates, How to Keep America Competitive, Wash. Post (February 25, 2007).

[5] Steve Case, Immigration Reform Can Spur Job Growth, U.S. News & World Report (Dec. 7, 2012),

http://www.usnews.com/opinion/articles/2012/12/07/steve-case-immigration-reform-must-include-stem-visas-.

[6] Jose Pagliery, America's Brain Drain Dilemma: Immigrant Students Who Leave, CNN Money (February 1, 2013), http://money.cnn.com/2013/01/31/smallbusiness/stem-immigrants/; Stuart Anderson, Nat’l Found. for Am. Policy, NFAP Policy Brief July 2013: The Importance of International Students to America 1-2 (2013).

[7] Anderson, supra note 6.

[8] Id.

[9] Anderson, supra note 6; Pagliery, supra note 6.

[10] See Immigration Innovation Act of 2013, S. 169, 113th Cong. (2013); STEM Jobs Act of 2012, H.R. 6429, 112th Cong. (2012) (as passed by House of Representatives, November 30, 2012); Benefits to Research and American Innovation through Nationality Statutes Act of 2012 (“BRAINS Act”), S. 3553, 112th Cong. (2012); Attracting the Best and Brightest Act of 2012, H.R. 6412, 112th Cong. (2012); Startup Act 3.0, H.R. 714, 113th Cong. (2013) (as introduced in H.R., February 14, 2013); White House Office of the Press Secretary, Fact Sheet: Fixing our Broken Immigration System so Everyone Plays by the Rules (2013) (available at http://www.whitehouse.gov/the-press-office/2013/01/29/fact-sheet-fixing-our-broken-immigration-system-so-everyone-plays-rules) (endorsing legislation to “‘Staple’ green cards to advanced STEM diplomas” and create a “Startup visa”).

[11] Joshua Wright, How Foreign-Born Graduates Impact the STEM Workforce Shortage Debate, Forbes (“More than 40 percent of the 25,000 STEM Ph.D.’s awarded in 2011 went to non-resident students… And only an estimated 30 percent of all foreign students end up staying on temporary work visas…”) (“http://www.forbes.com/sites/emsi/-2013/05/28/how-foreign-born-graduates-impact-the-stem-worker-shortage-debate/”); Ruth Ellen Wasem, Congressional Research Service, Immigration of Foreign Nationals with Science, Technology, Engineering, and Mathematics (STEM) Degrees 3-6 (2012).

[12] See Anderson, supra note 6 at 2 (“International students often become contributors to the U.S. economy as professors, researchers and entrepreneurs. Nearly 40 percent of immigrant entrepreneurs in recent venture-funded companies first entered the country as international students…”); Pagliery, supra note 6.

[13] Arendt, Imperialism at 301 (“The more highly developed a civilization, the more accomplished the world it has produced, the more at home men feel within the human artifice—the more they will resent everything they have not produced, everything that is merely and mysteriously given them. The human being who has lost his place in a community, his political status in the struggle of his time, and the legal personality which makes his actions and part of his destiny a consistent whole, is left with those qualities which usually can become articulate only in the sphere of private life and must remain unqualified, mere existence in all matters of public concern.”).

[14] See e.g. Anderson, supra note 6; Gates, supra note 4; Case, supra note 5; Jason DeParle, Favoring Immigration if Not the Immigrant, Wash. Post (May 8, 2011).

[15] See Arendt, The Human Condition at 154.

[16] See Arendt, The Human Condition at 154;

[18] http://explore.georgetown.edu/people/martinsf/

[19] DeParle, Supra note 11 (Martin “is less worried about how many immigrants come than about what rights they have.”); Susan F. Martin, A Nation of Immigrants 1 (2011).

[20] See generally Susan F. Martin, A Nation of Immigrants (2011).

[21] Martin, supra note 7, at 2 (citing Lawrence H. Fuchs, The American Kaleidoscope: Race, Ethnicity, and the Civic Culture 8 (1990)).

[22] The Human Condition 22.

[23] The Human Condition 22.

[24] The Human Condition at 7.

[25] The Human Condition at 136-139.

[26] Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition 7, 240-41  (2nd ed. 1958)

[27] The Human Condition 22.

[28] See On Revolution 281-282; Imperialism 296-301.

[29] See Martin at 4, 11, 41; Arendt, On Revolution at 281-282; Arendt, The Human Condition at 31, 84.

[30] See id.

[31] On Revolution at 246-49 (“The freedom of the people is in its private life … These words indeed spell out the death sentence for all organs of the people…”)

[32] Id. at 4, 287-309

[33] See id. at 4 (“the Pennsylvania model reflects what has been best in immigration to the United States”).

[34] The Human Condition 22

[35] The Human Condition 22

[36] See e.g. id.

[37] There may come a time where the “human condition,” a combination of labor, work, and action will no longer apply to people living on this earth. There may come a day when the consciousness of people are downloaded directly into silicon memory devices. David Eagleman, Silicon Immortality: Downloading Consciousness Into Computers, This Will Change Everything: Ideas that will Shape the Future 99 (John Brockman ed. 2009). In which case producing food, eating, and sleeping—i.e. the human condition of labor—would no longer be necessary. See id.; Arendt, The Human Condition at 7. Additionally, the potential for interaction between people creating something new—i.e. the human condition of action—is becoming less and less likely under the weight of consumerism and bureaucracy. Arendt, The Human Condition at 179. If labor or action are eliminated from the lives of future people, they may no longer be subject to the “human condition.” See id. Arendt calls a person that neither labors, nor acts in multiplicity, but merely creates durable objects, a “god.” Arendt, The Human Condition at 22. If individual consciences transcend the human condition, “gods” may be an appropriate label for them. However, cybernetics and consumerism have not yet advanced to the level where the human condition is no longer relevant.

[38] The Human Condition at 7 (“Labor is the activity which corresponds to the biological process of the human body...”)[38]

[39] See The Human Condition at 106-108.

[40] Id.

[41] See The Human Condition at 95, 106-108.

[42] See e.g. The Human Condition at 22.

[43] See The Human Condition at 7, 95, 106-107.

[44] The Human Condition at 108.

[45] See On Revolution 54, 136 (“affluence and wretchedness are only two sides of the same coin”); The Human Condition at 108.

[46] The Human Condition at 108.

[47] The Human Condition at 120 (“the perfect elimination of the pain and effort of labor would not only rob biological life of its most natural pleasures but deprive the specifically human life of its very liveliness and vitality.”)

[48] The Human Condition at 13.

[49] The Human Condition at 13.

[50] See The Human Condition 13, 95; see also Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Soveriegn Power and Bare Life 1 (Daniel Heller-Roazen)

[51] Arendt, The Human Condition at 19.

[52] See The Human Condition at 19, 95.

[53] The Human Condition at 95.

[54] The Human Condition at 136-139.

[55] Arendt, The Human Condition at 137.

[56] Acts “do not ‘produce,’ bring forth anything, they are as futile as life itself. In order to become worldly things, that is, deeds and facts and events and patterns of thoughts or ideas, they must first be seen, heard, and remembered and then transformed, reified as it were, into things—into sayings of poetry, the written page or the printed book, into paintings or sculpture, into all sorts of records, documents, and monuments.” The Human Condition at 95.

[57] The Human Condition at 95.

[58] The Human Condition at 95.

[59] The Human Condition at 95.

[60] The Human Condition at 137.

[61] The Human Condition at 137.

[62] Id.

[63] Id.

[64] The Human Condition at 71.      

[65] See id.; Margaret Jane Radin, Property and Personhood, 34 Stan. L. Rev. 957 (1982).

[66] The Human Condition at 66-67 (“The Human Condition at 71.”)

[67] The Human Condition at 167.

[68] See The Human Condition 206-207; Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 1140a1-20.

[69] Id.

[70] The Human Condition 124-125, 158.

[71] The Human Condition 9, 57, 137.

[72] The Human Condition 267.

[73] The Human Condition 171 (“a carpenter’s workmanship has failed when he fabricates a two-legged table”).

[74] See id.

[75] See id.

[76] Id.

[77] The Human Condition 171.

[78] The Human Condition at 13.

[79] See generally Martin Heidegger, The Question Concerning Technology, Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings from "Being and Time" (1927) to "The Task of Thinking" (1964) (David Farrell Krell ed. 2008).

[80] Id.

[81] The Human Condition at 156.

[82] The Human Condition at 156, Martin Heidegger, Question Concerning Technology, in The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays 16-17 (William Lovitt trans 1977).

[83] The Human Condition at 154.

[84] The Human Condition at 154.

[85] See The Human Condition at 154 (“Obviously there is no answer to the question Lessing once put to the utilitarian philosophers of his time: “And what is the use of use?”).

[86] Id.

[87] Id.

[88] Id.

[89] Id.

[90] The Human Condition at 154, 156.

[91] The Human Condition at 178.

[92] E.g. Hannah Arendt, On Revolution 182, 196 (1963)

[93] The Human Condition 13, 95; see also Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Soveriegn Power and Bare Life 1 (Daniel Heller-Roazen)

[94] The Human Condition 13, 95; see also Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Soveriegn Power and Bare Life 1 (Daniel Heller-Roazen)

[95] The Human Condition at 19

[96] Id.

[97] Arendt, The Human Condition at 19.

[98] Id.

[99] Id.

[100] See The Human Condition at 22.

[101] The Human Condition 19, 97, 186, 320.

[102] The Human Condition 178 ("The new always happens against the overwhelming odds of statistical laws and their probability, which for all practical, everyday purposes amounts to certainty; the new therefore always appears in the guise of a miracle.").

[103] The Human Condition at 240-241.

[104] Id.

[105] See id.

[106] Hannah Arendt, Postscriptum to Thinking, Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy 3 (Ronald Beiner ed. 1992) (“free acts are exceptional”).

[107] See The Human Condition 178.

[108] See Hannah Arendt, Postscriptum to Thinking 3 (“The will is either an organ of free spontaneity that interrupts all causal chains of motivation that would bind it or it is nothing but an illusion.”)

[109] The Human Condition at 25.

[110] The Human Condition at 25 (“Of all the activities necessary and present in human communities, only two were deemed to be political and to constitute what Aristotle called the bios politikos, namely action (praxis) and speech (lexis), out of which rises the realm of human affairs … from which everything merely necessary or useful is strictly excluded.”)

[111] See The Human Condition at 13; Hannah Arendt, Postscriptum to Thinking 3.

[112] The Human Condition at 13, 83-84.

[113] Id.

[114] Hannah Arendt, Imperialism: Part Two of the Origins of Totalitarianism 297 (1968)

[115] The Human Condition at 136-139.

[116] See Abraham H. Maslow, A Theory of Human Motivation, 50 Psych. R. 370, 373-74 (1943); Arendt, The Human Condition 13, 83-84.

[117] See The Human Condition at 13, 83-84; Abraham H. Maslow, A Theory of Human Motivation, 50 Psych. R. 370, 373-74 (1943).

[118] See The Human Condition at 13, 83-84; Maslow, supra note __ at 383.

[119] See Maslow, A Theory of Human Motivation 383; Arendt, The Human Condition at 41.

[120] “To belong to the few ‘equals’ (homoioi) meant to be permitted to live amon one’s peers; but the public realm itself, the polis, was permeated by a fiercely agonal spirit, where everybody had constantly to distinguish himself from all others, to show through unique deeds or achievements that he was the best of all (aien aristeuein).” Arendt, The Human Condition at 41.

[121] See Maslow, A Theory of Human Motivation 383; Arendt, The Human Condition at 10, 11, 31; see also Abraham H. Maslow, Toward a Psychology of Being 130-31, 218.

[122] A Theory of Human Motivation 380-84;

[123] See id.

[124] See id.; The Human Condition at 49 (“…for excellence, by definition, the presence of others is always required, and this presence needs the formality of the public, constituted by one’s peers, it cannot be the casual familiar presence of one’s equals or inferiors.”)

[125] See generally Maslow, A Theory of Human Motivation; Arendt, The Human Condition at 13; Arendt, Postscriptum to Thinking 3

[126] The Human Condition at 84 (“Because men were dominated by the necessities of life, they could win their freedom only through the domination of those whom the subjected to necessity by force.”), 119 (“the violent injustice of forcing one part of humanity into the darkness of pain and necessity … the price for absolute freedom from necessity is, in a sense, life itself, or rather the substitution of vicarious life for real life. Under the conditions of slavery, the great of the earth could even use their senses vicariously…”).

[127] Id. at 119.

[128] The Human Condition 31.

[129] The Human Condition at 130, 179, 202; compare Carl von Clausewitz, On War 119 (Anatol Rapoport ed., J.J. Graham trans., 1982). ("War is a mere continuation of policy by other means”); William R. Polk, Violent Politics: A History of Insurgency, Terrorism, and Guerilla War, from the American Revolution to Iraq (2008).

[130] The Human Condition 31.

[131] See The Human Condition 31.

[132] The Human Condition at 31.

[133] Arendt refers to slavery as a violent injustice. The Human Condition at 84. See also John Locke, Second Treatise on Government.

[134] On Revolution 66, 250, 252.

[135] On Revolution 243

[136] On Revolution 242

[137] On Revolution 252 (“with an almost weird precision those councils, soviets and Rate, which were to make their appearance in every genuine revolution throughout the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.”), 266, 268 (“The councils, obviously, were spaces of freedom.”), 270.

[138] See On Revolution 241-49 (“An enormous appetite for debate, for instruction, for mutual enlightenment and exchange of opinion, even if all these were to remain without immediate consequences on those in power, developed in these sections and societies.”).

[139] See e.g. Zizek Slavoj Zizek, The Universal Exception 51-53 (connecting Arendt’s approval of soviets with contemporary examples of the spontaneous emergence of “direct democracy,” including in the favelas of Brazil).

[140] See The Human Condition at 119

[141] See On Revolution 242-244.

[142] On Revolution 242-243 (“For the assumption of the Assembly then was that the Revolution had come to its end, that the societies which the Revolution had brought forward were no longer needed…”)

[143] See The Human Condition 324; On Revolution 24

[144] See e.g. Zizek Slavoj Zizek, The Universal Exception 51-53

[145] See id.; The Human Condition at 119

[146] See Arendt, The Human Condition at 13, 41.

[147] The Human Condition at 31, 36, 64, fn. 45, 83.

[148] The Human Condition 84.

[149] See id. at 84, 31, 92.

[150] The Human Condition at 31, 92.

[151] The Human Condition 31, 92 (“…the very wage is a pledge of slavery”)

[152] Id.

[153] Id.

[154] Id.

[155] Postscriptum to Thinking 3 (“free acts are exceptional”).

[156] Postscriptum to Thinking 3 (“free acts are exceptional”).

[157] Plato, Apology 37e-38a.

[158] On Revolution at 280-282.

[159] On Revolution at 280.

[160] On Revolution 281-282.

[161] See generally Susan F. Martin, A Nation of Immigrants (2011); see also Lawrence H. Fuchs, The American Kaleidoscope: Race, Ethnicity, and the Civic Culture 8-17 (1990);

[162] See DeParle, supra note 7; Martin, supra note 47 at 1.

[163] Fuchs, supra note 47 at 8-9.

[164] See id.

[165] Martin, supra note 47 at 11.

[166] Id. at 11.

[167] Id. at 20-21, 24.

[168] Id.

[169] Fuchs, supra note 47 at 17, Martin, supra note 47 at 26.

[170] See The Human Condition at 119;

[171] See On Revolution 124; 131.

[172] On Revolution 71.

[173] The Human Condition 71, 84; On Revolution 65-66.

[174] On Revolution 66

[175] See id.

[176] Martin at 1-2, 27-28.

[177] Id. at 27.

[178] Id.

[179] Id. at 27-28 (“To those who did not share the beliefs of the founders, Massachusetts applied a set of exclusionary policies.”).

[180] Id. at 28.

[181] Id. at 30.

[182] Id. 

[183] See Fuchs, supra note 47 at 8-9; Martin at 30.

[184] Martin at 30.

[185] See Fuchs, supra note 47 at 8-9; Martin at 30.

[186] See Martin at 30; Arendt, The Human Condition at 36-37, 83.

[187] See Martin at 30; Arendt, The Human Condition at 155, 305.

[188] Martin, supra note 47 at 4 (“[T]he Pennsylvania model reflects what has been best in immigration to the United States.”)

[189] Id. at 4, 41.

[190] Id. at 44, 48 (“The Frame of Government granted liberty of conscience to all who professed belief in a Creator…”).

[191] Id. at 41-42, 48-49.

[192] Id. at 56.

[193] Id. at 41; Fuchs supra note 47 at 14.

[194] See Martin, supra note 47 at 41, 56, 59.

[195] See Martin, supra note 47 at 41, 56, 59.

[196] See Martin, supra note 47 at 41, 56, 59; On Revolution 282 (“The trouble lies in the lack of public spaces to which people at large would have entrance and from which an elite could be selected, or rather, where it could select itself.”)

[197] Id.; See also On Revolution at 246-49, 280.

[198] See The Human Condition 324; On Revolution 241 (“the Constitution itself provided a public space only for the representatives of the people.”).

[199] See id.

[200] Martin, supra note 47 at 4, 287-309.

[201] See id.; see also Fuchs, supra note 47.

[202] See INA § 101(a)(15), 8 U.S.C. § 1101(a)(15) (1952), § 214(b), 8 U.S.C. § 1184(b) (2000); see also Steel on Immigration Law § 3:1 (2d ed.).

[203] See id.; 1 Immigr. Law and Defense § 3:1 (2013 ed.).

[204] See INA § 214(h), 8 U.S.C. § 1184(h) (2000); 1 Immigration Law Service 2d § 4:2.

[205] Lawful Permanent Resident (LPR), U.S. Citizenship and Immigration Servs. (last accessed March 30, 2013) http://www.uscis.gov/portal/site/uscis/menuitem.5af9bb95919f35e66f614176543f6d1a?vgnextoid-=07065c4f635f010VgnVCM1000000ecd190aRCRD&vgnextchannel=b328194d3e88d010VgnVCM10000048f3d6a1RCRD.

[206] INA § 203(a)(2), 8 U.S.C. § 1153(a)(2) (1995); see also INA § 204(a), 8 U.S.C. § 1154(a) (2009).

[207] Lawful permanent residents are generally not considered aliens seeking admission, unless than have been out of the country for over 12 months.

[208] INA § 316, 8 U.S.C. § 1427 (1990).

[209] See INA § 201(d), 8 U.S.C. § 1151(d) (1990); Nicaraguan Public Adjustment and Central American Relief Act (NACARA), Pub. L. 105-100, 111 Stat. 2160 (1997) (reducing spaces for “other workers” by 5,000).

[210] In 2012, 143,998 employment based immigrant statuses were granted. Of those, only 65,918 went to principal applicants, while 78,080 went spouses and children. U.S. Department of Homeland Security, Office of Immigration Statistics, Yearbook of Immigration Statistics tbl. 7 (2013) (http://www.dhs.gov/yearbook-immigration-statistics-2012-legal-permanent-residents).

[211] INA § 203(b), 8 U.S.C. § 1153(b) (1990).

[212] See id.

[213] Id. Typically, each preference category uses its full allotment. Ruth Ellen Wasem, Cong. Research Serv., Numerical Limits on Employment-Based Immigration: Analysis of the Per-Country Ceilings 5 (2011) (available at http://www.fas.org/sgp/crs/homesec/R42048.pdf).

[214] INA § 202(a)(2), 8 U.S.C. § 1152(a)(2) (1990).

[215] Visa Bulletin for March 30, 2013, U.S. Dept. of State (February 8, 2013) (http://travel.state.gov/visa/-bulletin/bulletin_5885.html).

[216] This is calculation is based on priority dates for Chinese priority-two employment-based immigration applicants. See id.

[217] This is calculation is based on priority dates for Indian priority-two employment-based immigration applicants. See id.

[218] Stuart Anderson, Should Congress Raise the H-1B Cap?, Testimony of Stuart Anderson, Executive Director: National Foundation for American Policy before the House Subcommittee on Immigration, Border Security, and Claims 2 (Mar. 30, 2006) (available at http://www.nfap.com/researchactivities/-articles/Testimony033006.pdf).

[219]  Jeanne Batalova, Migration Policy Inst., The Growing Connection Between Temporary and Permanent Immigration Systems 5-6 (2006); see also Lauren E. Sasser, Waiting in Immigration Limbo: The Federal Court Split over Suits to Compel Action on Stalled Adjustment of Status Applications, 76 Fordham L. Rev. 2511, 2519 (2008). 

[220] Anderson, supra note 23.

[221] See INA § 245(k), 8 U.S.C. § 1255(k) (1990). Only a small proportion of employment-based immigrants are new arrivals--only 12 percent in 2012. Supra note 17 at tbl. 6.

[222] See id.; Anderson supra note 23.

[223] See e.g. Matloff, supra note 12 at 855 (2003).

[224] INA § 214(a), 8 U.S.C. § 1184(a) (1990).

[225] See generally INA §

[226] INA § 101(A)(15)(F), 8 U.S.C. § 1101(a)(15)(F) (2006) (admission with intent to study at a U.S. University);  8 C.F.R. § 214.2(f)(1)(i) (2011); INA §§101(a)(15)(H)(i)(b), 214(i), 8 U.S.C. §§ 1101, 1184(i) (defining “specialty occupation”).

[227] INA § 101(a)(15)(F)(i), 8 U.S.C. § 1101(a)(15)(F)(i) (2006); 8 C.F.R. § 214.2(f)(6) (2011).

[228] See INA § 245(k),  8 U.S.C. § 1255(k) (1990).

[229] See supra notes 22-30.

[230] H. Ronald Klasko, American Competitiveness in the 21st Century: H-1bs and Much More, 77 No. 47 Interpreter Releases 1689 (“The new law addresses the delay issue by allowing the new employer to commence employment of the foreign national upon the filing of the new petition rather than upon its approval); American Competitiveness in the Twenty-first Century Act of 2000,” Pub.L. 106–313, Title I, Oct. 17, 2000, 114 Stat. 1251 § 105, INA § 214(n) 8 U.S.C. § 1184(m) (200).

[231] Christopher Fulmer, A Critical Look at the H-1b Visa Program and Its Effects on U.S. and Foreign Workers: A Controversial Program Unhinged from Its Original Intent, 13 Lewis & Clark L. Rev. 823, 857 (2009).

[232] 8 C.F.R. § 214.2(f)(10)(ii).

[233] 8 C.F.R. § 214.2(f)(10)(ii)(C); The Programmer's Guild, Inc. v. Chertoff, 130 S.Ct. 2090 (2010) (denying cert. to a challenge to the 17-month extension for STEM students); see also 73 Fed. Reg. 18944 (Apr. 8, 2008) (providing 90-day, “cap-gap” extension for students seeking h-1b status).

[234] See id.

[236] Joseph Weiner, The Specialty Occupation Requirement for the H-1b Visa, L.A. Law., September 2010, at 14; Batalova, supra note __.

[237] U.S. Citizenship and Immigration Servs., USCIS Reaches Fiscal Year 2013 H-1B Cap (June 12, 2012), http://www.uscis.gov/portal/site/uscis/template.PRINT/menuitem.5af9bb95919f35e66f614176-543f6d1a/?vgnextoid=ee9f3f93131e7310VgnVCM100000082ca60aRCRD&vgnextchannel=68439c7755cb9010VgnVCM10000045f3d6a1RCRD.

[238] INA § 214(g)(1)(A).

[239] West Group, Congress Clears H-1b Legislation in Surprise Move; President Clinton Expected to Sign, 77 NO. 39 Interpreter Releases 1437, 1438; “American Competitiveness in the Twenty-first Century Act of 2000,” Pub.L. 106–313, Title I, Oct. 17, 2000, 114 Stat. 1251 § 102 (amending INA § 214(g)(1)(A),  8 U.S.C. 1184(g)(1)(a)).

[240] Id.

[241] U.S. Citizenship and Immigration Servs., supra note 42.

[242] Id.

[243] INA § 101(a)(15)(F)(i), 8 U.S.C. § 1101(a)(15)(F)(i) (2006); 8 C.F.R. § 214.2(f)(6) (2011).

[244] See id.

[245] Norman Matloff, On the Need for Reform of the H-1b Non-Immigrant Work Visa in Computer-Related Occupations, 36 U. Mich. J.L. Reform 815, 817 (2003).

[246] Id.

[247] See e.g. Christopher Fulmer,  A Critical Look at the H-1b Visa Program and Its Effects on U.S. and Foreign Workers-A Controversial Program Unhinged from Its Original Intent, 13 Lewis & Clark L. Rev. 823, 857 (2009); Norman Matloff, On the Needfor Reform of the H-JB Non-Immigrant Work Visa in Computer-Related Occupations, 36 U. Mich. J.L. Reform 815, 868-69 (2003).

[248] Nathan Cochrane, Fairfax IT: Fame, Fortune, and a Bit of Nirvana, Fairfax IT, available at http://linuxtoday.com/infrastructure/1999071300209PS (last visited July 13, 1999).

[249] See id.; Martin at 30.

[251] See INA § 101(a)(15)(F)(i), 8 U.S.C. § 1101(a)(15)(F)(i) (2006); 8 C.F.R. § 214.2(f)(6) (2011).

[252] Hannah Arendt, Collective Responsibility 158 (1968).

[253] The Human Condition at 63.

[254] On Revolution at 103.

[255] See id.

[256] Hannah Arendt, Imperialism: Part Two of the Origins of Totalitarianism 296-297 (1968).                   

[257] Nathan Cochrane, Fairfax IT: Fame, Fortune, and a Bit of Nirvana, Fairfax IT, available at http://linuxtoday.com/infrastructure/1999071300209PS (last visited July 13, 1999).

[258] Generally speaking temporary workers, and LPR’s, can be deported if they commit a crime involving moral turpitude and commit a crime which a sentence of one year or longer may be imposed a sentence, or commit two or more crimes involving moral turpitude. INA § 237(a)(2), 8 U.S.C. 1227(a)(2) (1990). A “crime involving moral turpitude” is a common law term of art that generally refers to crimes that are relatively severe and require a certain level of scienter. 23 A.L.R. Fed. 480(2013).

[259] Hannah Arendt, Imperialism: Part Two of the Origins of Totalitarianism 296-297 (1968).                   

[260] See Anderson, supra note 6 at 2; Pagliery, supra note 6; Wright, supra note 11; Wasem, supra note 11.

[261] See On Revolution at 103.

[262] See id.

[263] See The Human Condition 84.

[264] INA § 101(a)(15)(F)(i), 8 U.S.C. § 1101(a)(15)(F)(i) (2006); 8 C.F.R. § 214.2(f)(6) (2011); Norman Matloff, On the Need for Reform of the H-1b Non-Immigrant Work Visa in Computer-Related Occupations, 36 U. Mich. J.L. Reform 815, 817 (2003); 6 Richard Freeman, “The Market for Scientists and Engineers,” NBER Reporter, no. 3 (Summer 2007).

[265] Ilana J. Drummond, Hiring International Workers in Today's Economy: New Challenges and Strategies, Employing International Workers, 2010 Edition: Leading Lawyers on Understanding Recent Immigration Trends, Navigating the Visa Process, and Meeting Compliance Requirements 69 (Aspatore ed. 2010).

[266] Ilana J. Drummond, Hiring International Workers in Today's Economy: New Challenges and Strategies, Employing International Workers, 2010 Edition: Leading Lawyers on Understanding Recent Immigration Trends, Navigating the Visa Process, and Meeting Compliance Requirements 69 (Aspatore ed. 2010).

[267] See id.

[268] See id.

[269] See e.g. STEM Jobs Act of 2012, H.R. 6429, 112th Cong. (2012) (as passed by House of Representatives, November 30, 2012); Immigration Innovation Act of 2013, S. 169, 113th Cong. (2013); Benefits to Research and American Innovation through Nationality Statutes Act of 2012 (“BRAINS Act”), S. 3553, 112th Cong. (2012); Attracting the Best and Brightest Act of 2012, H.R. 6412, 112th Cong. (2012); Startup Act 3.0, H.R. 714, 113th Cong. (2013) (as introduced in H.R., February 14, 2013); Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act,  S. 744, 113th Cong. (2013-2014) (as passed by Senate June 27, 2013).

[270] Startup Act 3.0, H.R. 714, 113th Cong. (2013) (as introduced in H.R., February 14, 2013); Immigration Innovation Act of 2013, S. 169, 113th Cong. (2013); Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act,  S. 744, 113th Cong. (2013-2014) (as passed by Senate June 27, 2013)

[271] Preface to the Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act, S. 744, 113th Cong. (2013-2014) (as passed by Senate June 27, 2013).

[272] It is exactly 1,197 pages long. Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act, S. 744, 113th Cong at 1. (2013-2014) (as passed by Senate June 27, 2013), available at http://www.gpo.gov/fdsys/pkg/BILLS-113s744pap/pdf/BILLS-113s744pap.pdf.

[273] See Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act, S. 744, 113th Cong § 1103, 2231, 2307(b)(N) (2013-2014) (as passed by Senate June 27, 2013).

[274] See Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act, S. 744, 113th Cong § 2307(b)(N) (2013-2014) (as passed by Senate June 27, 2013); INA § 201(b)(1), 8 U.S.C. § 1153(b)(1) (1990).

[275] See id.

[276] See Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act, S. 744, 113th Cong § 2307(b)(N) (2013-2014) (as passed by Senate June 27, 2013); INA § 201(b)(1), 8 U.S.C. § 1153(b)(1) (1990).

[277] Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act, S. 744, 113th Cong § 2306.

[278] See id.; Stuart Anderson, Nat’l Found. for Am. Policy, Waiting and More Waiting: America’s Family and Employment-Based Immigration System 1, 2, 7 (2011).

[279] See Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act, S. 744, 113th Cong § 2306 (2013-2014).

[280] Id. at § 2304, 2306.

[281] Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act, S. 744, 113th Cong § 2304

[282] See id. at § 2304, 2306; INA § 203(b), 8 U.S.C. § 1153(b) (1990).

[283] See Immigration Innovation Act of 2013, S. 169, 113th Cong. § 216B (2013); Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act, S. 744, 113th Cong § 2307(b).

[284] See id.

[285] Immigration Innovation Act of 2013, S. 169, 113th Cong. § 216B (2013).

[286] Id.

[287] Id.

[288] Id.

[289] Id.

[290] Id.; “[T]here is no consensus on the definition of STEM fields within academia or federal agencies.” Ruth Ellen Wasem, Congressional Research Service, Immigration of Foreign Nationals with Science, Technology, Engineering, and Mathematics (STEM) Degrees 25 (2012).

[291] See id.

[292] Id. at § 216B(c).

[293] See id.; 26 USC § 3304(a)(14)(A)(1990).

[294] Immigration Innovation Act of 2013, S. 169, 113th Cong. at § 216B(e).

[295] Immigration Innovation Act of 2013, S. 169, 113th Cong. at § 5.

[296] See id.

[297] See Norman Matloff, On the Need for Reform of the H-1b Non-Immigrant Work Visa in Computer-Related Occupations, 36 U. Mich. J.L. Reform 815, 817 (2003); 6 Richard Freeman, “The Market for Scientists and Engineers,” NBER Reporter, no. 3 (Summer 2007).

[298] Hannah Arendt, Collective Responsibility 158 (1968).

[299] See supra note 257; INA § 237(a)(2), (6), 8 U.S.C. 1227(a)(2), (6); 23 A.L.R. Fed. 480.

[300] See INA Sec. 316(a), 8 U.S.C. 1427(a) (1990).

[301] Id.

[302] See Border Security, Economic Opportunity, and Immigration Modernization Act, S. 744, 113th Cong § 2306, 2307(b)(N) (2013-2014) (as passed by Senate June 27, 2013); INA § 201(b)(1), 8 U.S.C. § 1153(b)(1) (1990).

[303] See Immigration Innovation Act of 2013, S. 169, 113th Cong. § 216B.

[304] See id.

[305] See id.; Fulmer, supra note 230.

[306] Immigration Innovation Act of 2013, S. 169, 113th Cong. § 216B.